Ethics and Community ~~ Aldo Leopold
Something a little different - an essay about ethics, community, private property and social obligation. Hope you enjoy, NB
The Land Ethic
by Aldo Leopold
1949
[ This essay is excerpted from Aldo Leopold's book A Sand County Almanac. ]
When god-like Odysseus returned from the wars in Troy, he hanged all on one rope a
dozen slave-girls of his household whom he suspected of misbehavior during his
absence.
This hanging involved no question of propriety. The girls were property. The disposal of
property was then, as now, a matter of expediency, not of right and wrong.
Concepts of right and wrong were not lacking from Odysseus' Greece: witness the
fidelity of his wife through the long years before at last his black-prowed galleys clove
the wine-dark seas for home. The ethical structure of that day covered wives, but had
not yet been extended to human chattels. During the three thousand years which have
since elapsed, ethical criteria have been extended to many fields of conduct, with
corresponding shrinkages in those judged by expediency only.
THE ETHICAL SEQUENCE
This extension of ethics, so far studied only by philosophers, is actually a process in
ecological evolution. Its sequences may be described in ecological as well as well as in
philosophical terms. An ethic, ecologically, is a limitation on freedom of action in the
struggle for existence. An ethic, philosophically, is a differentiation of social from antisocial conduct. These are two definitions of one thing. The thing has its origin in the
tendency of interdependent individuals or groups to evolve modes of co-operation. The
ecologist calls these symbioses. Politics and economics are advanced symbioses in
which the original free-for-all competition has been replaced, in part, by co-operative
mechanisms with an ethical content.
The complexity of co-operative mechanisms has increased with population density, and
with the efficiency of tools. It was simpler, for example, to define the anti-social uses of
sticks and stones in the days of the mastodons than of bullets and billboards in the age
of motors.
The first ethics dealt with the relation between individuals; the Mosaic Decalogue is an
example. Later accretions dealt with the relation between the individual and society. The
Golden Rule tries to integrate the individual to society; democracy to integrate social
organization to the individual.
There is as yet no ethic dealing with man's relation to land and to the animals and plants
which grow upon it. Land, like Odysseus' slave-girls, is still property. The land-relation is
still strictly economic, entailing privileges but not obligations.
The extension of ethics to this third element in human environment is, if I read the
evidence correctly, an evolutionary possibility and an ecological necessity. It is the third
step in a sequence. The first two have already been taken. Individual thinkers since the
days of Ezekiel and Isaiah have asserted that the despoliation of land is not only
inexpedient but wrong. Society, however, has not yet affirmed their belief. I regard the
present conservation movement as the embryo of such an affirmation.
An ethic may be regarded as a mode of guidance for meeting ecological situations so
new or intricate, or involving such deferred reactions, that the path of social expediency
is not discernible to the average individual. Animal instincts are modes of guidance for
the individual in meeting such situations. Ethics are possibly a kind of community
instinct in-the-making.
THE COMMUNITY CONCEPT
All ethics so far evolved rest upon a single premise that the individual is a member of a
community of interdependent parts. His instincts prompt him to compete for his place in
that community, but his ethics prompt him also to co-operate (perhaps in order that
there may be a place to compete for).
The land ethic simply enlarges the boundaries of the community to include soils, waters,
plants, and animals, or collectively: the land.
This sounds simple: do we not already sing our love for and obligation to the land of the
free and the home of the brave? Yes, but just what and whom do we love? Certainly not
the soil, which we are sending helter-skelter down river. Certainly not the waters, which
we assume have no function except to turn turbines, float barges, and carry off sewage.
Certainly not the plants, of which we exterminate whole communities without batting an
eye. Certainly not the animals, of which we have already extirpated many of the largest
and most beautiful species. A land ethic of course cannot prevent the alteration,
management, and use of these 'resources,' but it does affirm their right to continued
existence, and, at least in spots, their continued existence in a natural state.
In short, a land ethic changes the role of Homo sapiens from conqueror of the landcommunity to plain member and citizen of it. It implies respect for his fellow-members,
and also respect for the community as such.
In human history, we have learned (I hope) that the conqueror role is eventually selfdefeating. Why? Because it is implicit in such a role that the conqueror knows, ex
cathedra, just what makes the community clock tick, and just what and who is valuable,
and what and who is worthless, in community life. It always turns out that he knows
neither, and this is why his conquests eventually defeat themselves.
In the biotic community, a parallel situation exists. Abraham knew exactly what the land
was for: it was to drip milk and honey into Abraham's mouth. At the present moment, the
assurance with which we regard this assumption is inverse to the degree of our
education.
The ordinary citizen today assumes that science knows what makes the community
clock tick; the scientist is equally sure that he does not. He knows that the biotic
mechanism is so complex that its workings may never be fully understood.
That man is, in fact, only a member of a biotic team is shown by an ecological
interpretation of history. Many historical events, hitherto explained solely in terms of
human enterprise, were actually biotic, interactions between people and land. The
characteristics of the land determined the facts quite as potently as the characteristics
of the men who lived on it.
Consider, for example, the settlement of the Mississippi valley. In the years following the
Revolution, three groups were contending for its control: the native Indian, the French
and English traders, and the American settlers. Historians wonder what would have
happened if the English at Detroit had thrown a little more weight into the Indian side of
those tipsy scales which decided the outcome of the colonial migration into the canelands of Kentucky. It is time now to ponder the fact that the cane-lands, when subjected
to the particular mixture of forces represented by the cow, plow, fire, and axe of the
pioneer, became bluegrass. What if the plant succession inherent in this dark and
bloody ground had, under the impact of these forces, given us some worthless sedge,
shrub, or weed? Would Boone and Kenton have held out? Would there have been any
overflow into Ohio, Indiana, Illinois, and Missouri? Any Louisiana Purchase? Any
transcontinental union of new states? Any Civil War?
Kentucky was one sentence in the drama of history. We are commonly told what the
human actors in this drama tried to do, but we are seldom told that their success, or the
lack of it, hung in large degree on the reaction of particular soils to the impact of the
particular forces exerted by their occupancy. In the case of Kentucky, we do not even
know where the bluegrass came from -- whether it is a native species, or a stowaway
from Europe.
Contrast the cane-lands with what hindsight tells us about the Southwest, where the
pioneers were equally brave, resourceful, and persevering. The impact of occupancy
here brought no bluegrass, or other plant fitted to withstand the bumps and buffetings of
hard use. This region, when grazed by livestock, reverted through a series of more and
more worthless grasses, shrubs, and weeds to a condition of unstable equilibrium. Each
recession of plant types bred erosion; each increment to erosion bred a further
recession of plants. The result today is a progressive and mutual deterioration, not only
of plants and soils, but of the animal community subsisting thereon. The early settlers
did not expect this: on the ciƩnegas of New Mexico some even cut ditches to hasten it.
So subtle has been its progress that few residents of the region are aware of it. It is
quite invisible to the tourist who finds this wrecked landscape colorful and charming (as
indeed it is, but it bears scant resemblance to what it was in 1848).
This same landscape was 'developed' once before, but with quite different results. The
Pueblo Indians settled the Southwest in pre-Columbian times, but they happened not to
be equipped with range livestock. Their civilization expired, but not because their land
expired.
In India, regions devoid of any sod-forming grass have been settled, apparently without
wrecking the land, by the simple expedient of carrying the grass to the cow, rather than
vice versa. (Was this the result of some deep wisdom, or was it just good luck? I do not
know.)
In short, the plant succession steered the course of history; the pioneer simply
demonstrated, for good or ill, what successions inhered in the land. Is history taught in
this spirit? It will be, once the concept of land as a community really penetrates our
intellectual life.
THE ECOLOGICAL CONSCIENCE
Conservation is a state of harmony between man and land. Despite nearly a century of
propaganda, conservation still proceeds at a snail's pace; progress still consists largely
of letterhead pieties and convention oratory. On the back forty we still slip two steps
backward for each forward stride.
The usual answer to this dilemma is 'more conservation education.' No one will debate
this, but is it certain that only the volume of education needs stepping up? Is something
lacking in the content as well?
It is difficult to give a fair summary of its content in brief form, but, as I understand it, the
content is substantially this: obey the law, vote right, join some organizations, and
practice what conservation is profitable on your own land; the government will do the
rest.
Is not this formula too easy to accomplish anything worth-while? It defines no right or
wrong, assigns no obligation, calls for no sacrifice, implies no change in the current
philosophy of values. In respect of land use, it urges only enlightened self-interest. Just
how far will such education take us? An example will perhaps yield a partial answer.
By 1930 it had become clear to all except the ecologically blind that southwestern
Wisconsin's topsoil was slipping seaward. In 1933 the farmers were told that if they
would adopt certain remedial practices for five years, the public would donate CCC
labor to install them, plus the necessary machinery and materials. The offer was widely
accepted, but the practices were widely forgotten when the five-year contract period
was up. The farmers continued only those practices that yielded an immediate and
visible economic gain for themselves.
This led to the idea that maybe farmers would learn more quickly if they themselves
wrote the rules. Accordingly the Wisconsin Legislature in 1937 passed the Soil
Conservation District Law. This said to farmers, in effect: We, the public, will furnish you
free technical service and loan you specialized machines, if you will write your own rules
for land-use. Each county may write its own rules, and these will have the force of law.
Nearly all the counties promptly organized to accept the proffered help, but after a
decade of operation, no county has yet written a single rule. There has been visible
progress in such practices as strip-cropping, pasture renovation, and soil liming, but
none in fencing woodlots against grazing, and none in excluding plow and cow from
steep slopes. The farmers, in short, have selected those remedial practices which were
profitable anyhow, and ignored those which were profitable to the community, but not
clearly profitable to themselves.
When one asks why no rules have been written, one is told that the community is not
yet ready to support them; education must precede rules. But the education actually in
progress makes no mention of obligations to land over and above those dictated by selfinterest. The net result is that we have more education but less soil, fewer healthy
woods, and as many floods as in 1937.
The puzzling aspect of such situations is that the existence of obligations over and
above self-interest is taken for granted in such rural community enterprises as the
betterment of roads, schools, churches, and baseball teams. Their existence is not
taken for granted, nor as yet seriously discussed, in bettering the behavior of the water
that falls on the land, or in the preserving of the beauty or diversity of the farm
landscape. Land use ethics are still governed wholly by economic self-interest, just as
social ethics were a century ago.
To sum up: we asked the farmer to do what he conveniently could to save his soil, and
he has done just that, and only that. The farmer who clears the woods off a 75 per cent
slope, turns his cows into the clearing, and dumps its rainfall, rocks, and soil into the
community creek, is still (if otherwise decent) a respected member of society. If he puts
lime on his fields and plants his crops on contour, he is still entitled to all the privileges
and emoluments of his Soil Conservation District. The District is a beautiful piece of
social machinery, but it is coughing along on two cylinders because we have been too
timid, and too anxious for quick success, to tell the farmer the true magnitude of his
obligations. Obligations have no meaning without conscience, and the problem we face
is the extension of the social conscience from people to land.
No important change in ethics was ever accomplished without an internal change in our
intellectual emphasis, loyalties, affections, and convictions. The proof that conservation
has not yet touched these foundations of conduct lies in the fact that philosophy and
religion have not yet heard of it. In our attempt to make conservation easy, we have
made it trivial.
SUBSTITUTES FOR A LAND ETHIC
When the logic of history hungers for bread and we hand out a stone, we are at pains to
explain how much the stone resembles bread. I now describe some of the stones which
serve in lieu of a land ethic.
One basic weakness in a conservation system based wholly on economic motives is
that most members of the land community have no economic value. Wildflowers and
songbirds are examples. Of the 22,000 higher plants and animals native to Wisconsin, it
is doubtful whether more than 5 per cent can be sold, fed, eaten, or otherwise put to
economic use. Yet these creatures are members of the biotic community, and if (as I
believe) its stability depends on its integrity, they are entitled to continuance.
When one of these non-economic categories is threatened, and if we happen to love it,
we invent subterfuges to give it economic importance. At the beginning of the century
songbirds were supposed to be disappearing. Ornithologists jumped to the rescue with
some distinctly shaky evidence to the effect that insects would eat us up if birds failed to
control them. The evidence had to be economic in order to be valid.
It is painful to read these circumlocutions today. We have no land ethic yet, but we have
at least drawn nearer the point of admitting that birds should continue as a matter of
biotic right, regardless of the presence or absence of economic advantage to us.
A parallel situation exists in respect of predatory mammals, raptoral birds, and fisheating birds. Time was when biologists somewhat overworked the evidence that these
creatures preserve the health of game by killing weaklings, or that they control rodents
for the farmer, or that they prey only on 'worthless' species. Here again, the evidence
had to be economic in order to be valid. It is only in recent years that we hear the more
honest argument that predators are members of the community, and that no special
interest has the right to exterminate them for the sake of a benefit, real or fancied, to
itself. Unfortunately this enlightened view is still in the talk stage. In the field the
extermination of predators goes merrily on: witness the impending erasure of the timber
wolf by fiat of Congress, the Conservation Bureaus, and many state legislatures.
Some species of trees have been 'read out of the party' by economics-minded foresters
because they grow too slowly, or have too low a sale value to pay as timber crops:
white cedar, tamarack, cypress, beech, and hemlock are examples. In Europe, where
forestry is ecologically more advanced, the non-commercial tree species are recognized
as members of the native forest community, to be preserved as such, within reason.
Moreover some (like beech) have been found to have a valuable function in building up
soil fertility. The interdependence of the forest and its constituent tree species, ground
flora, and fauna is taken for granted.
Lack of economic value is sometimes a character not only of species or groups, but of
entire biotic communities: marshes, bogs, dunes, and 'deserts' are examples. Our
formula in such cases is to relegate their conservation to government as refuges,
monuments, or parks. The difficulty is that these communities are usually interspersed
with more valuable private lands; the government cannot possibly own or control such
scattered parcels. The net effect is that we have relegated some of them to ultimate
extinction over large areas. If the private owner were ecologically minded, he would be
proud to be the custodian of a reasonable proportion of such areas, which add diversity
and beauty to his farm and to his community.
In some instances, the assumed lack of profit in these 'waste' areas has proved to be
wrong, but only after most of them had been done away with. The present scramble to
reflood muskrat marshes is a case in point.
There is a clear tendency in American conservation to relegate to government all
necessary jobs that private landowners fail to perform. Government ownership,
operation, subsidy, or regulation is now widely prevalent in forestry, range management,
soil and watershed management, park and wilderness conservation, fisheries
management, and migratory bird management, with more to come. Most of this growth
in governmental conservation is proper and logical, some of it is inevitable. That I imply
no disapproval of it is implicit in the fact that I have spent most of my life working for it.
Nevertheless the question arises: What is the ultimate magnitude of the enterprise? Will
the tax base carry its eventual ramifications? At what point will governmental
conservation, like the mastodon, become handicapped by its own dimensions? The
answer, if there is any, seems to be in a land ethic, or some other force which assigns
more obligation to the private landowner.
Industrial landowners and users, especially lumbermen and stockmen, are inclined to
wail long and loudly about the extension of government ownership and regulation to
land, but (with notable exceptions) they show little disposition to develop the only visible
alternative: the voluntary practice of conservation on their own lands.
When the private landowner is asked to perform some unprofitable act for the good of
the community, he today assents only with outstretched palm. If the act costs him cash
this is fair and proper, but when it costs only forethought, open-mindedness, or time, the
issue is at least debatable. The overwhelming growth of land-use subsidies in recent
years must be ascribed, in large part, to the government's own agencies for
conservation education: the land bureaus, the agricultural colleges, and the extension
services. As far as I can detect, no ethical obligation toward land is taught in these
institutions.
To sum up: a system of conservation based solely on economic self-interest is
hopelessly lopsided. It tends to ignore, and thus eventually to eliminate, many elements
in the land community that lack commercial value, but that are (as far as we know)
essential to its healthy functioning. It assumes, falsely, I think, that the economic parts
of the biotic clock will function without the uneconomic parts. It tends to relegate to
government many functions eventually too large, too complex, or too widely dispersed
to be performed by government.
An ethical obligation on the part of the private owner is the only visible remedy for these
situations.
No comments:
Post a Comment